Re: Comparative Smootheology, II
Hi John,
Thanks for your emails. I’m delighted that you’re looking at the paper and
welcome your comments; particularly as I know that you actually want to use
this stuff!
Okay, so on to your comments …
Firstly, Chen’s definitions. Yes, he does define “differentiable spaces” in
several different ways. Let me see if I can hunt them all down. I’ll repeat
them all here since bytes are cheap and it’ll make it easier to comment on
them.
1973
By a convex -region (or, simply a convex region), we mean a closed
convex region in . A convex -region consists of a single
point.
Definition. A differentiable space is a Hausdorff space equipped with
a family of maps called plots which satisfy the following conditions:
(a) Every plot is a continuous map of the type , where
is a convex region.
(b) If is also a convex region (not necessarily of the same dimension
as ) and if is a map, then
is also a plot.
(c) Each map is a plot.
So you’re right: I missed the Hausdorff condition here. That’s extremely
annoying on two counts: firstly that I missed it, and secondly because it
mucks up the functors. My functor to Early Chen Spaces used the indiscrete
topology (essentially to make it irrelevant). I can’t do that any more. I’ll
have to think about how much of a difference that makes. Of course, to a
certain extent then it doesn’t make any difference since no one actually uses
these spaces as anyone who is aware of Chen’s original definition is almost
certainly aware of his later definitions and would prefer to use those.
1975
By a convex region we mean a closed convex set in for some
finite .
Definition. A predifferentiable space is a topological space
equipped with a family of maps called plots which satisfy the following
conditions:
(a) Every plot is a continuous map of the type , where
is a convex region.
(b) If is also a convex region (not necessarily of the same dimension
as ) and if is a map, then
is also a plot.
(c) Each map is a plot.
Remark. in [1973], a predifferentiable space is called a “differentiable
space”. We propose to amend the definition of a differentiable space by
adding the following condition:
(d) Let be a continuous map and let
be a family of maps, , being
convex regions, such that a function on is if and only if
each is on . If each
is a plot of , then itself is a plot of .
I had not come across this paper before and it is extremely interesting.
First, in his recollection of what is now a predifferentiable space Chen
drops the Hausdorff condition. Thus what I called “Early Chen Spaces” are
these predifferentiable spaces. Secondly, and much much more importantly, is
his introduction of condition d. This appears to be a sheaf condition but it
is not; it is much stronger. By Kriegl and Michor’s result on curves in
convex regions (see later for more on this), we could take the family of
functions to be the family of smooth curves in . Thus condition
d is saying, “any continuous map which is a plot when restricted to smooth
curves is a plot”.
Interestingly, Chen retains the assumption of an underlying topology.
1977
The symbols , , , will denote convex sets. All convex
sets will be finite dimensional. They will serve as models, i.e. sets whose
differentiable structure is known.
…
Definition 1.2.1 A differentiable space is a set equipped with a
family of set maps called plots, which satisfy the following conditions:
(a) Every plot is a map of the type , where can be
arbitrary.
(b) If is a plot and if is a
map, then is a plot.
(c) Every constant map from a convex set to is a plot.
(d) Let be a set map. If is an open covering of
and if each restriction is a plot, then is itself a
plot.
Again, you are right. I did not spot the fact that he has here dropped the
requirement that the convex sets be closed. They are just arbitrary convex
sets of finite dimension, and not necessarily embedded in Euclidean space (not
that that matters). Comparing with the 1975 definition, we see that the
fourth condition is now a sheaf condition.
I do have the 1986 paper in front of me. Here’s the definition from that.
1986
We take as the model category the one whose ojects are convex subsets with
nonempty interiour in , , and whose morphisms
are maps.
…
Definition 1.1. A space is a set equipped with a family of
set maps called plots, which satisfy the following conditions:
(a) Every plot is a map of the type where is a convex set.
(b) If is a plot and if is also a convex set (not
necessarily of the same dimension as ), then, for every map
, is also a plot.
(c) Every constant map from a convex set to is a plot.
(d) Let be an open convex covering of a convex set , and let
be a set map. If each restriction is a plot,
then itself is a plot.
Up to trivial rephrasing, this is the same as the 1977 definition.
You ask:
Is there some reason you made these changes?
Yes. Sheer ignorance! Stupidity cannot be ruled out either. I simply did
not spot the myriad of changes. In my defence, I would say that rather than
simply copying the definitions in the paper I was trying to standardise the
language.
We appear to have four definitions with certain characteristics:
- 1973, no sheaf-like condition, topology, Hausdorff, closed domains.
- 1975a, no sheaf-like condition, topology, not necessarily Hausdorff, closed
domains.
- 1975b, strong sheaf-like condition, topology, not necessarily Hausdorff,
closed domains.
- 1977 (and 1986), sheaf condition, no topology, arbitrary domains.
By “arbitrary” I mean still convex, but not assumed to be closed.
Phew!
I got one of these, at least. My “Early Chen Spaces” are the 1975a
definition. But you’re right, my “Chen Spaces” are not on the list. Whoops.
However, I think that one can simply delete the word “closed” from my
definition of a Chen space to get the 1977 definition and this would not
require any other changes to the mathematics. I’ll have to check that, of
course, but I’m reasonably confident. The other definitions will require a
little thought.
I’d certainly consider putting them all in my paper but I think it warrants a
little reorganisation. Perhaps in the main flow of the paper it would be best
to concentrate on the last definition and then have a separate section
comparing all the different variants of Chen space.
Does that go some way to answering your question on definitions?
On to the equivalence (or not) of Chen and Souriau spaces. You ask:
Are your categories “Chen” and “Souriau” equivalent or not?
It seems like probably not. You don’t seem to prove this: instead,
you construct some adjunctions between them and show they’re not
equivalences. But, maybe you understand the situation well enough
to easily figure this out! Maybe it’s easier to show there’s no
equivalence that acts as the identity on the underlying sets and functions.
In principle there could be some sneakier equivalence.
I’m actually interested in showing that Chen’s 1977 category is
not equivalent to “Souriau”, but I’ll take whatever words of advice
you can offer!
I think that they are not equivalent. Let’s see if we can prove this. To
shorten the notation, let be the category of Chen spaces (1977
definition) and the category of Souriau spaces (diffeological
spaces).
The first thing to do is to rule out your “sneaky equivalence”. Suppose we
have functors and . Suppose that these define an equivalence of categories. Then
in particular, they take terminal objects to terminal objects. We therefore
have natural isomorphisms
and vice versa, and this works on morphisms. Therefore up to natural
isomorphism, and are set-preserving. We can make this strictly true if we want essentially by regarding and as lying
over two copies of and using and to identify the two copies in a
(possibly) non-standard fashion.
So any equivalence has to define a set-preserving one. Let us now assume that our functors are set-preserving. This means that and are the same subset of and
similarly for . This means that the compositions and are
exactly the identity functors on their respective categories.
Now, I think, we can show that the functor from Chen spaces to Souriau spaces
is the one that I describe in my paper. In fact, this is easier with the
assumption of closedness dropped.
The set of plots of a Chen space, , is precisely the union of the sets where runs over the family of convex regions with their standard Chen structure. A similar statement for Souriau spaces holds only with the family of open sets (in Euclidean spaces).
Let be an open convex subset of some Euclidean space. We can give this
a canonical Chen structure and a canonical Souriau structure; both of which
are characterised by the fact that they contain the identity map. As
and are the identity functors, we see that the identity map is contained in all of
so we deduce that, with absolutely horrendous notation, and .
Now as Souriau spaces satisfy the sheaf condition, the Souriau plots are
completely determined by the subfamily where runs over the family of open
convex sets. We therefore have
More generally, we see that if is an open subset of some Euclidean space
then using the sheaf conditions
where is given the canonical Chen structure wherein all inclusions of
convex subsets are plots.
Hence the functor is the functor that I
describe in my paper.
Now we arrive at a contradiction. I’m pretty sure that even with the modified
definition of Chen spaces, my example of two distinct Chen spaces with the
same underlying Souriau space remains valid. Thus the functor cannot be
part of an equivalence of categories and so the categories of Chen spaces and
Souriau spaces are not equivalent.
(Insert end-of-proof symbol here)
Right, I worked that out more or less as I wrote it so there’s probably bits
that I’ve overlooked. It’ll probably look a bit neater when run through iTeX
(you can do that without posting it on the cafe). Let me know if you’re
convinced!
Now, on to Kriegl and Michor’s theorem. I simplified the statement of the
theorem in their book since that deals with convex subsets in arbitrary
convenient vector spaces. In doing so, perhaps I lost a little precision.
What I was not careful about was defining the interior of a convex set. What
I ought to have said was that this was the abstract interior, not the
interior as embedded in some arbitrary . If one embeds the
abstract convex set in its “natural” affine space, then this abstract interior
is the interior that you inherit from the topology on the affine space. I
guess that this is what Chen had in mind in the 1986 paper.
So you were right to pick up on that, but it was my error in being imprecise
and misquoting Kriegl and Michor.
Right, that’s probably enough to be going on with for now. It’s getting near
lunchtime here and I’m getting hungry.
Best,
Andrew
Re: Comparative Smootheology, II
Hi John,
Thanks for your emails. I’m delighted that you’re looking at the paper and welcome your comments; particularly as I know that you actually want to use this stuff!
Okay, so on to your comments …
Firstly, Chen’s definitions. Yes, he does define “differentiable spaces” in several different ways. Let me see if I can hunt them all down. I’ll repeat them all here since bytes are cheap and it’ll make it easier to comment on them.
1973
So you’re right: I missed the Hausdorff condition here. That’s extremely annoying on two counts: firstly that I missed it, and secondly because it mucks up the functors. My functor to Early Chen Spaces used the indiscrete topology (essentially to make it irrelevant). I can’t do that any more. I’ll have to think about how much of a difference that makes. Of course, to a certain extent then it doesn’t make any difference since no one actually uses these spaces as anyone who is aware of Chen’s original definition is almost certainly aware of his later definitions and would prefer to use those.
1975
I had not come across this paper before and it is extremely interesting. First, in his recollection of what is now a predifferentiable space Chen drops the Hausdorff condition. Thus what I called “Early Chen Spaces” are these predifferentiable spaces. Secondly, and much much more importantly, is his introduction of condition d. This appears to be a sheaf condition but it is not; it is much stronger. By Kriegl and Michor’s result on curves in convex regions (see later for more on this), we could take the family of functions to be the family of smooth curves in . Thus condition d is saying, “any continuous map which is a plot when restricted to smooth curves is a plot”.
Interestingly, Chen retains the assumption of an underlying topology.
1977
Again, you are right. I did not spot the fact that he has here dropped the requirement that the convex sets be closed. They are just arbitrary convex sets of finite dimension, and not necessarily embedded in Euclidean space (not that that matters). Comparing with the 1975 definition, we see that the fourth condition is now a sheaf condition.
I do have the 1986 paper in front of me. Here’s the definition from that.
1986
Up to trivial rephrasing, this is the same as the 1977 definition.
You ask:
Yes. Sheer ignorance! Stupidity cannot be ruled out either. I simply did not spot the myriad of changes. In my defence, I would say that rather than simply copying the definitions in the paper I was trying to standardise the language.
We appear to have four definitions with certain characteristics:
By “arbitrary” I mean still convex, but not assumed to be closed.
Phew!
I got one of these, at least. My “Early Chen Spaces” are the 1975a definition. But you’re right, my “Chen Spaces” are not on the list. Whoops. However, I think that one can simply delete the word “closed” from my definition of a Chen space to get the 1977 definition and this would not require any other changes to the mathematics. I’ll have to check that, of course, but I’m reasonably confident. The other definitions will require a little thought.
I’d certainly consider putting them all in my paper but I think it warrants a little reorganisation. Perhaps in the main flow of the paper it would be best to concentrate on the last definition and then have a separate section comparing all the different variants of Chen space.
Does that go some way to answering your question on definitions?
On to the equivalence (or not) of Chen and Souriau spaces. You ask:
I think that they are not equivalent. Let’s see if we can prove this. To shorten the notation, let be the category of Chen spaces (1977 definition) and the category of Souriau spaces (diffeological spaces).
The first thing to do is to rule out your “sneaky equivalence”. Suppose we have functors and . Suppose that these define an equivalence of categories. Then in particular, they take terminal objects to terminal objects. We therefore have natural isomorphisms
and vice versa, and this works on morphisms. Therefore up to natural isomorphism, and are set-preserving. We can make this strictly true if we want essentially by regarding and as lying over two copies of and using and to identify the two copies in a (possibly) non-standard fashion.
So any equivalence has to define a set-preserving one. Let us now assume that our functors are set-preserving. This means that and are the same subset of and similarly for . This means that the compositions and are exactly the identity functors on their respective categories.
Now, I think, we can show that the functor from Chen spaces to Souriau spaces is the one that I describe in my paper. In fact, this is easier with the assumption of closedness dropped.
The set of plots of a Chen space, , is precisely the union of the sets where runs over the family of convex regions with their standard Chen structure. A similar statement for Souriau spaces holds only with the family of open sets (in Euclidean spaces).
Let be an open convex subset of some Euclidean space. We can give this a canonical Chen structure and a canonical Souriau structure; both of which are characterised by the fact that they contain the identity map. As and are the identity functors, we see that the identity map is contained in all of
so we deduce that, with absolutely horrendous notation, and .
Now as Souriau spaces satisfy the sheaf condition, the Souriau plots are completely determined by the subfamily where runs over the family of open convex sets. We therefore have
More generally, we see that if is an open subset of some Euclidean space then using the sheaf conditions
where is given the canonical Chen structure wherein all inclusions of convex subsets are plots.
Hence the functor is the functor that I describe in my paper.
Now we arrive at a contradiction. I’m pretty sure that even with the modified definition of Chen spaces, my example of two distinct Chen spaces with the same underlying Souriau space remains valid. Thus the functor cannot be part of an equivalence of categories and so the categories of Chen spaces and Souriau spaces are not equivalent.
(Insert end-of-proof symbol here)
Right, I worked that out more or less as I wrote it so there’s probably bits that I’ve overlooked. It’ll probably look a bit neater when run through iTeX (you can do that without posting it on the cafe). Let me know if you’re convinced!
Now, on to Kriegl and Michor’s theorem. I simplified the statement of the theorem in their book since that deals with convex subsets in arbitrary convenient vector spaces. In doing so, perhaps I lost a little precision. What I was not careful about was defining the interior of a convex set. What I ought to have said was that this was the abstract interior, not the interior as embedded in some arbitrary . If one embeds the abstract convex set in its “natural” affine space, then this abstract interior is the interior that you inherit from the topology on the affine space. I guess that this is what Chen had in mind in the 1986 paper.
So you were right to pick up on that, but it was my error in being imprecise and misquoting Kriegl and Michor.
Right, that’s probably enough to be going on with for now. It’s getting near lunchtime here and I’m getting hungry.
Best, Andrew