Formal and Material Inference
Posted by David Corfield
A distinction is made within philosophy between formal and material inference. The first of these operates purely through the logical form of the relevant propositions, whereas the second relies on conceptual content occurring within them.
A classic example of a formal inference is , therefore . Substitute any propositions for and and the inference goes through. The conjunction is a piece of logical vocabulary. By contrast, the thinking goes, that is west of implies that is east of is a piece of material inference, relying on the relation between the non-logical concepts, ‘east’ and ‘west’. Substitute ‘older’ for ‘east’ and ‘larger’ for ‘west’ and the inference fails.
The philosopher Wilfred Sellars famously asserted that in such cases we’re not merely employing a tacit proposition, i.e., here ‘If is west of , then is east of ’, instantiating it and then using modus ponens. For Sellars, and those following him, like Robert Brandom, material inference is primary; only for a limited portion of our inferential practices has humankind managed to extract formal inference schemas.
But then how to decide what is ‘logical’ and what ‘non-logical’? As an adherent of dependent type theory, can’t I hold any inference carried out in that system to be formal?
Say I have judged and , where is a predicate on . Then defining for , , I can now judge , using standard type-theoretic rules.
Rewriting this inference in something closer to English, we find the syllogism:
is a , No s are , therefore is not .
As a valid syllogism, any substitution should do, so let’s choose a type, , say . is an element of , so let’s say Jane. is a property of people, let’s say ‘being in this house’.
Then we have the inference
Jane is a person. No people are in the house. Therefore Jane is not in the house.
OK, why this example?
Because it, or something very like it, appears already in the literature:
- González de Prado Salas, J., de Donato Rodríguez, X. & Zamora Bonilla, J. 2017. Inferentialism, degrees of commitment, and ampliative reasoning. Synthese. (paper)
if I am committed to endorsing the proposition ‘The house is empty,’ I will also be committed to endorsing ‘Jane is not in the house.’
…if one wants to characterize inferentially the content associated with non-logical vocabulary, one has to consider inferences that are not formally good, but that are made good by the content of the (non-logical) concepts they involve–that is, materially good inferences (like the inference about the empty house mentioned above).
Surely it can’t be that the translation between ‘No people are in the house’ and ‘The house is empty’ changes the inference from being formal to being material. When I learn to say of a house that it’s empty, I know that it’s defined to mean that they’re aren’t people in the house. I must learn that the presence of doors within doesn’t count. And I’d better know that Jane is a person. I wouldn’t have concluded from the house’s emptiness that just anything is not in the house.
Another case of claimed material inference, one given by Sellars himself, is that from ‘This is red’ to ‘This is colored’. On p. 17 of Chapter 1 of my book, which OUP has now made available, I sketch a type-theoretic account. To be able to use such language, to know that there is a type of colours, that red is a colour, that some things have a colour, when all this is written type-theoretically, I don’t see why we can’t take it too as a piece of formal inference.
Re: Formal and Material Inference
The red ball case is, I claim, an instance of a general inference scheme which says that if we have two types, and , which are sets, and a relation between them, , then given , and that is the case, then is inhabited, and so the propositional truncation is true.
So, for some choices of the components of this set-up we have special words to employ for the latter proposition: the object is colored; the person is a parent; the item is used; the house is occupied; the number is composite, and so on.
To insist that such instances of the inference scheme are to be counted as material will require a difficult line to be drawn as to acceptable rewriting. Presumably all allow the rewriting that enables us to consider the inference from ‘Jill is happy, and Jack is too’ to ‘Jack is happy’ as formal.