Large Sets 3
Posted by Tom Leinster
Previously: Part 2. Next: Part 4.
Inherent in set theory is the notion of well-ordered set. If you think about sets for long enough, well-orderings are bound to show up. In this post I’ll explain why, and I’ll summarize some of the fundamental facts about well-orderings — the least standard of which is an adjunction between sets and well-ordered sets.
There are no large sets this time, but what we do here will be needed in later instalments.
Pick up any book on set theory, and you’ll find significant amounts of order theory (and I include in that the theory of ordinals). Order is everywhere. I used to find that mysterious, but I think I have it clearer now.
There are two ways in which order arises inevitably in set theory. Both are to do with injections.
First, for any set , the collection of subsets of is naturally ordered by inclusion. This ordered set is a Boolean algebra, accounting for the prominence of Boolean algebras in set theory.
Second, and with just a little poetic licence, the relation on sets is a well-ordering. (Here means that there exists an injection .) Precise statements are that any nonempty family of sets has a -least element, or that for any set , the set of isomorphism classes of sets smaller than is well-ordered by . This accounts for the prominence of well-orderings in set theory.
Experience shows that when dealing with well-ordered sets, the most important notion of “map” is a quite restrictive one: an order-embedding whose image is downwards closed (or an “initial segment”, in the jargon). When I say a map of well-ordered sets, that’s always what I’ll mean.
This notion of map is actually so restrictive that for any well-ordered sets and , there is at most one map . I’ll write if there exists a map .
So, the category of well-ordered sets is a preorder. Indeed, it’s a “well-preorder”: any nonempty family of well-ordered sets has a -least element.
At the start of this post, I promised to explain an important adjunction between well-ordered sets and sets. I was being a bit of a tease, because there are no interesting adjunctions between and the usual category of sets. The forgetful functor certainly doesn’t have an adjoint.
However, there is a highly significant adjunction between and the preorder . By , I mean the category whose objects are sets, and with one map when and no maps if not. To emphasize that the category is also a preorder, I’ll write it now as . There is a forgetful functor
that takes the underlying set of a well-ordered set. It’s well-defined on maps (that is, ) because order-embeddings are injective. And it’s this forgetful functor that has an adjoint.
The adjoint of is a left adjoint,
It’s defined on a set by taking to be the set equipped with an initial well-order, that is, a well-order such that for any other well-order on ,
To see that this definition of is valid, we have to run through a little argument. First of all, the axiom of choice (which is part of ETCS, and which I assume throughout) implies that there is at least one well-order on . And I noted above that any nonempty family of well-ordered sets has a -least element. So has an initial well-order. In general, will have many initial well-orders, since given any one of them, you can permute the elements of to get another. But the usual universal property argument shows that it’s unique up to isomorphism: if and are initial well-orders on then
The adjointness says that for a set and a well-ordered set ,
The left-to-right implication is somewhat trivial: apply to the inequality and note that . The right-to-left implication uses the definition of initial well-order.
For example, suppose that is countably infinite. There are many isomorphism classes of countably infinite well-ordered sets, but the initial one is . (It’s traditional to write for when it’s being regarded as a well-ordered set.) So . The adjointness relation for says that a well-ordered set is infinite if and only if .
Incidentally, since and are total orders, the adjointness can equivalently be stated as
To a category theorist, it’s maybe a bit funny to see the left adjoint on the right of the inequality and the right adjoint on the left. But this statement is just the contrapositive of the earlier formulation of adjointness.
So, we have adjoint functors
Since , this adjunction restricts to an equivalence of categories
By an “initial well-ordered set” I mean one isomorphic to for some set , or more directly, one that’s -least of its cardinality.
I phrased the last few paragraphs in a categorical way, guessing that most readers of The -Category Café would find that enlightening rather than… endarkening? But whether you look at things categorically or not, the important point is that there’s a correspondence
So you can, if you want, identify sets with initial well-ordered sets. In ZFC-based developments of set theory, it’s standard to define a cardinal as an initial ordinal. That definition relies on particularities of membership-based set theory that I want to avoid here because I’m doing things “neutrally”. But behind the traditional cardinals-as-ordinals definition, there’s an idea expressible in neutral terms, and it’s exactly this correspondence.
Next time
In parts 4 and 5, we’ll contemplate the ladder of alephs, which involves a different — but also important — pair of back-and-forth processes between sets and well-ordered sets.
Set category
I’m trying to understand what “the collection of all sets preordered by cardinal inequality” means. Is it a category whose Obj = {sets}, but homsets are of size 1 or 0, with #Hom(X,Y)=1 exactly when there exists an injection X->Y?