Higher Compactness
Posted by Mike Shulman
Higher category theorists enjoy categorifying stuff. That word can mean lots of things, but one thing it can mean is to take some familiar 1-category, embed it naturally into a higher category, and then try to extend some of the appropriate theory. And one of the threads in topos theory is to do this with topology, where we start with the 1-category of topological spaces.
So how do we categorify topological spaces? The first thing we do (normally) is to replace them by locales. A locale is a lattice that behaves like the open-set lattice of a topological space: it has finite intersections, arbitrary unions, and the former distribute over the latter. A big class of topological spaces are uniquely determined by their open-set lattice, so this doesn’t lose very much, and it makes it easier to categorify since a lattice is, after all, a (0,1)-category. (It’s possible to skip this step by using ionads, but let’s not get into that today.)
Now for lots of reasons that I also don’t want to get into, the appropriate categorification of a locale is a Grothendieck topos: a locally presentable category with finite limits and arbitrary colimits, where the former distribute over the latter in some well-defined way. Hopefully this is mostly intuitive, limits and colimits being categorifications of intersections and unions in lattice theory. This definition generalizes to higher categories as well, at least to the -case, and we have full embeddings However, these embeddings are not the identity, i.e. the lattice that is a locale is not itself a (1,1)-topos, but has to be made into one by passing to sheaves. Similarly, for , an -topos is not itself an -topos, but has to be made into one by passing to -sheaves.
The question I want to discuss today is, how do we categorify notions like compactness and local compactness from topology to higher toposes?
Compactness of a space is clearly a property of its open-set lattice : whenever we have a family of opens such that is the top element of the lattice, then there is a finite subfamily with that property. An equivalent way to say that is if we have a directed family of opens such that , then there is some with . (To go from the first to the second, consider the directed family of finite unions.)
And another equivalent way to say that is that the map , defined by and for all , preserves directed unions. This map is the right adjoint to the inverse image induced by the continuous map , so it’s actually a fairly canonical sort of beast. Moreover, this phrasing tells us that compactness is not really a property of the space , but rather of the map . For an arbitrary continuous map , we can consider the property that (the right adjoint of the inverse image ) preserves directed unions, and this defines the property of being a proper map.
Now for an -topos , let’s write for the -category that it “is”. A morphism of such toposes is essentially by definition an adjoint pair of functors , and so we have an obvious categorification of properness: we can ask that preserve filtered colimits. In particular, the terminal topos has being the category of -groupoids (0-groupoids being sets and -groupoids being truth values), and is the “global sections” functor , so it is natural to consider “compactness” of to mean that this functor preserves filtered colimits.
The interesting thing is that if is an ordinary topological space (or locale), then compactness in the usual sense (i.e. preserving directed unions) does not imply that its corresponding -topos of sheaves is compact in this sense (i.e. need not preserve filtered colimits for )! The following counterexample can be found in Sketches of an Elephant: let be the quotient of with both copies of identified and both copies of identified. Then is a quotient of a compact space, hence compact, but it is not “strongly compact”: if is the quotient of with both copies of identified for or , then the colimit of the diagram is the terminal object, which has a global section, but none of the has a global section.
In 1-topos theory, a morphism of 1-toposes such that preserves filtered colimits is said to be tidy, and if then is said to be strongly compact. I found this very mysterious until I learned about -toposes, and realized that compactness/properness and strong-compactness/tidiness were just the cases and of a tower of conditions on -topoi for .
Presumably there are toposes, even toposes of sheaves on topological spaces, which are -compact but not -compact for all . It would be interesting to try to find some. However, if a space is not only (0-)compact but also Hausdorff (which is equivalently to say that its diagonal is also proper), then it is automatically -compact for all , including . So this hierarchy is only nontrivial for “ill-behaved” spaces (for some meaning of “ill-behaved”).
There is also a “dual” hierarchy which yields a tower of more familiar conditions on topological spaces. It turns out that -compactness is equivalent to asking that the functor is an -indexed functor. If we instead ask that the inverse image functor have a left adjoint which is -indexed, then we get the definition of when is locally -connected. For 1-toposes, we get ordinary local connectedness, while for 0-toposes we get local inhabitedness. The latter is also called openness of . Again, I found the connection between openness and local connectedness in 1-topos theory very confusing until I realized that they were the cases of a hierarchy.
Now we come to something that is more conjectural: what about local compactness? It’s a bit trickier to characterize local compactness of a space in terms of its open set lattice, but it can be done. In any lattice with directed unions, define (pronounced is way below ) to mean that whenever is the union of a directed family , then there is some with . In , this holds if there is a compact set with (and the converse holds if is locally compact). Then local compactness of can be phrased as the requirement that every is the join of all opens that are way below it.
This gives the definition of a locally compact locale. A more categorification-friendly characterization involves the lattice of order-ideals in , i.e. directed lower sets. The “principal ideal” map is the free cocompletion of under directed unions, and so since has directed unions, this map has a left adjoint . It turns out that is locally compact, in the sense described above, just when has a left adjoint.
When we categorify, the role of is played by the Ind-completion of , which is again its free cocompletion under filtered colimits. Now we can ask whether has a left adjoint, and call this something like local -compactness of .
As before, it turns out that local (0-)compactness does not imply local 1-compactness: essentially the same counterexample applies. And again as before, there is a stronger notion which does suffice for local 1-compactness, called stable local compactness. This means that the way-below relation is preserved by finite intersections (including the empty intersection, which implies that the space is compact). In the topos-theoretic literature, local 1-compactness of a locale is called meta-stable local compactness.
As far as I know, local -compactness for has not been studied (but I would love to be wrong!). Here are some basic questions about it that would be nice to answer:
- Are there examples of locally -compact spaces that are not locally -compact, for all ?
- Can local -compactness, at least for spaces or locales, be expressed in a way that looks more evidently like a “local” sort of -compactness?
- Are stably locally compact locales automatically locally -compact for all , just as compact Hausdorff locales are automatically -compact for all ?
- In the cases , the locally -compact -toposes are exactly the exponentiable ones. Is this true for as well?
Re: Higher Compactness
Does anything interesting happen to the compactness theorem in logic when you increase ?
In view of the compactness-ultrafilter connection, perhaps we need the answer to your query to Tom.